Tuesday, May 20, 2025

PHILOSOPHY AFTER METAPHYSICS

  

"Metaphysical logic isn't just about formal deduction. It's about exploring the fundamental structures of reality through the structure of thought."

Exploring fundamental structures through philosophical logic? A philosophical logic being distinct from a formal logic in terms of it progressing through concepts and their negation. I would classify this as a rationalist project unaware of its own irony.


To “explore the fundamental structures of reality through the structure of thought”, as metaphysical logic claims to do, is already to blur the line between ontology and epistemology—but more damningly, to assume a deep and lawful isomorphism between how we think and what is. That’s the rationalist assumption at the heart of the metaphysical enterprise: that the mind’s conceptual movement can track—or even determine—the real. It presumes a deep correspondence between the structures of thought and the structures of being, as if contradiction in language must mirror tension in the world. But this is a faith in reason untethered from the conditions of its own emergence. 

 Once we recognize that thought is a biological process—shaped by evolutionary pressures, subject to bias, error, and cultural conditioning—the irony becomes clear: metaphysical logic relies on the very cognitive apparatus it refuses to interrogate. Crucially, though, to say that thought is biological is not to make a metaphysical claim in return, but to offer an empirical one—grounded in observation, subject to revision, and always provisional. This is the difference: the metaphysician speaks from a position of necessity, the scientist from contingency. One builds castles in conceptual air; the other builds models in the dirt, knowing they might collapse tomorrow.

 
To continue to practice “philosophical logic” in this mode today—outside of formal systems, and untethered from empirical input—is not just antiquated, it becomes a kind of cognitive theatre: mistaking the elegance of thought’s self-relation for insight into the world itself.

If metaphysical logic claims to describe the fundamental structures of reality, then it's competing with physics and biology—and losing.

Physics describes the structure of spacetime, matter, causality.

Biology explains form, function, and even emergent phenomena like mind.

Cognitive science is mapping consciousness and reason from the inside out.

If metaphysical/philosophical logic tries to do this kind of work from the armchair, it’s overstepping—doing inferior science without experiments.

Kant, Hegel, Schelling, and others were engaging in what now looks like proto-theory: an attempt to describe the world before empirical methods matured.

So a metaphysical logic becomes/ is reduced to:

Mere historically importance, but outdated.

It's epistemologically weak, because it lacks testing or constraint.

Is redundant, because the sciences have taken over its domain.


So the metaphysician says: "you're right, we can’t know things-in-themselves via metaphysics. But we can:

"Clarify the conditions under which experience and knowledge are possible.

"Explore the logical structures of cognition, which science itself presupposes.

"Thus, we declare, metaphysics is not a rival to science, but its philosophical infrastructure."


But why think philosophers, rather than psychologists, cognitive scientists, or evolutionary biologists, are best equipped to explain how perception and cognition happen?

Psychology shows how perception develops and varies (think: visual illusions, development of object permanence).

Cognitive science models pattern recognition, mental representation, and reasoning using computation.

Linguistics has empirically grounded what philosophers could only speculate about: deep structures, deep insights into grammar, cognitive constraints.

Neuroscience and evolutionary biology explain why certain cognitive structures evolved—not as metaphysical necessities, but as adaptations.

So the philosopher's claim about the "necessary preconditions of experience" may just be highly evolved regularities of one species’ cognition. Contingent, not necessary. Explorable, not intuited.

The metaphysician deems to speak: "The worry is: if science is based on observation, and observation is conditioned by the mind, then science has hidden assumptions."

Rebuttal: But why not let the sciences themselves explore those “hidden assumptions”? Don’t psychology and neurobiology now tell us more about how humans actually think?

From the sciences themselves, we have learned:

Human reasoning is fallible, context-sensitive, and evolutionarily shaped.

“Logic” isn’t some universal architecture; it’s a subset of cognition, one evolved for social coordination, survival, or prediction.

Much human thought is non-logical, heuristic, or emotionally biased.


So even logic—the stronghold of the metaphysician—turns out to be just one historically evolved cognitive mode, not a transcendental structure.

Why does the metaphysician assume that his language of metaphysics is best suited to that task of informing us about reality?

There’s an elitism baked into philosophy:

That conceptual reflection is superior to empirical investigation.

That armchair reasoning can deduce universal truths from the structure of thought.

That philosophy has a unique, privileged access to what must be.


But under empirical scrutiny, these claims collapse. Philosophy doesn't have a special method for accessing necessary truths about reality or mind—it just had a head start in asking the questions before science had the tools.

Where does this leave the metaphysical philosopher:

Most of the philosophical line is reduced to historical influence, but is no longer epistemologically authoritative. Metaphysical answers have been replaced.

Philosophy might still help clarify scientific assumptions—but only in tandem with science, not above it. Philosophy must now play "follow the leader," and that which is leading, is not philosophy.

Maybe we don’t need this kind of transcendental reflection anymore? Science has inherited its responsibilities and performs them better. Let philosophy focus on ethics, aesthetics, and meaning-making—its humanist domains. Where philosophy lives on, it lives on only as critique, but a critique that is no longer conscious of itself. It fails to grasp the fallacy of its deployment of a selective skepticism. Where philosophy believes itself to be breaking into domains of liberation, it often ends up advocating a dogmatic idealism. Of this it is not aware, it cannot see itself, even though it claims to have a master sight of everything else.

Paradigm shift:  

The conditions of experience and knowledge are not metaphysical—they’re biological.

But the metaphysicians will cry out, "this is a reduction that has been tried before."

Here the philosopher is deceived by his meta-critique. The fact that he can find incompleteness in the emerging narratives of the sciences, emboldens him to swing his metaphysics like a bat. He longs to entangle men in his metaphysical paradoxes, believing that by doing such, he is penetrating into the true nature of reality. This is a deep metaphysical pathology.

"Science is incomplete → therefore, metaphysics must be necessary → therefore, let us return to the metaphysical theater."

The deception lies in believing that because a critique of science can be mounted (e.g., “science doesn’t explain consciousness fully,” “reality is more than measurement”), it follows that metaphysical speculation is therefore valid or necessary. This is a category mistake—substituting conceptual ingenuity for empirical traction. It is the patheticness of an intellectual opportunism: the metaphysician capitalizes on the limits of scientific explanation not to push inquiry forward, but to reassert a kind of epistemic sovereignty he never truly earned.

The seduction of metaphysics: Once science begins to make the world clearer, the metaphysician reintroduces mystery—not as a problem to solve, but as proof that the world resists clarity. What he really wants is to occupy the place of highest authority in the hierarchy of knowledge.

It becomes a kind of:

Epistemic brinkmanship (“if we don’t know everything, we know nothing”),

Conceptual bullying (using paradox to destabilize rather than deepen),

Intellectual nostalgia (a longing for when questions felt more profound than they were answerable)
.

The metaphysical paradox becomes not a tool of inquiry, but a weapon of ambiguity.

The strategic use of incompleteness/ how the metaphysician seeks to survive:

1) Science is inherently incomplete (true, and always will be).

2) There are explanatory gaps (e.g., qualia, first-person experience, free will)."

3) Therefore, something beyond science is needed.

This logic is structurally identical to theological arguments from ignorance:

We don’t know how X works → Therefore, God/metaphysics.

But this is not a demonstration of something else being true—only that we don't know yet. It’s an invitation to persist in inquiry, not to default to abstraction.

What place does philosophy still have?

It legitimately survives as critique, but it must do better to become aware of itself and its limitations, it must put on the gown of humility.

Instead of desperately swinging its metaphysical bat, it should:

-Acknowledge explanatory gaps as live scientific frontiers.

-Use formal models, computational simulations, and empirical research to gradually close them.

-Treat philosophical reflection as hypothesis formation, not as final word.


[Its role may be reduced to a critical creativity-- but critical creativity does have value.]

In this light, metaphysics doesn't “penetrate reality” but floats above it—untethered, ornamental, and increasingly optional.

Philosophy After Metaphysics:

Philosophy, having surrendered its claim to ontological authority, need not vanish—it must evolve. Its future lies not in asserting what is, but in clarifying, interrogating, and improving the tools by which we come to know. In this role, philosophy becomes:

- A critical lens on the language, models, and metaphors that shape scientific practice.

- A semantic scalpel for distinguishing useful concepts from confusions, detecting category errors, and resolving pseudo-problems.

- A methodological ally—a collaborator with science, not a competitor to it.


Philosophers can ask:  

-What are the implications of this biological view of knowledge for ethics, identity, and culture?  

-How should humans live, now that we understand ourselves as evolved, contingent, and embedded systems? 

-Can we clarify the conceptual assumptions at the foundations of science to improve its explanatory power and increase its coherence?


But if philosophers return to the paradox-labyrinth of metaphysics in search of ontological supremacy, they’re not leading—they’re lingering and laboring in a paradigm that the natural sciences have largely sublated.

The metaphysical impulse survives on a kind of intellectual nostalgia—the belief that reality has hidden depths accessible only through a priori reflection. But the sciences have made this strategy obsolete by exposing how even our deepest intuitions—about time, causality, the self—are not revelations of some timeless structure but artifacts of evolutionary design and neural implementation. Cognitive science, for instance, doesn’t merely offer another theory of mind; it dissolves the Cartesian conceit entirely, showing that the unified self is a constructed illusion, stitched together by adaptive systems with no need for metaphysical substantiation. Where metaphysics once speculated about the soul or essence, neuroscience and developmental biology now offer grounded, testable models that render such concepts redundant.

More fatally, metaphysics lacks any method for self-correction. It confuses interpretive ingenuity for epistemic progress, spinning conceptual webs with no empirical anchor. The sciences, by contrast, are disciplined by error—they advance not by the elegance of their abstractions, but by their capacity to be proven wrong. Metaphysics mistakes this fallibility for weakness, but in truth, it is the engine of discovery. When physics revised its view of space and time, or when biology overturned essentialist views of species, it was because its models met resistance in the world. Metaphysics meets only itself. And in doing so, it no longer explains reality—it merely dramatizes our ignorance.

 

-

-

-